DONALD TRUMP, the populist American president-elect,
wants to deport undocumented immigrants. Podemos, the populist Spanish party,
wants to give immigrants voting rights. Geert Wilders, the populist Dutch
politician, wants to eliminate hate-speech laws. Jaroslaw Kaczynski, the
populist Polish politician, pushed for a law making it illegal to use the
phrase “Polish death camps”. Evo Morales, Bolivia’s populist president, has
expanded indigenous farmers’ rights to grow coca. Rodrigo Duterte, the
Philippines’ populist president, has ordered his police to execute suspected
drug dealers. Populists may be militarists, pacifists, admirers of Che Guevara
or of Ayn Rand; they may be tree-hugging pipeline opponents or drill-baby-drill
climate-change denialists. What makes them all “populists”, and does the word
actually mean anything?
Widespread use of the term “populism” dates to the
1890s, when America’s Populist movement pitted rural populations and the
Democratic Party against the more urban Republicans. (It was also used to refer
to Russia’s 19th-century narodnichestvo movement, which largely comprised self-hating
intellectuals with a crush on the peasantry.) In the 1950s academics and
journalists began applying it more broadly to describe everything from fascist
and communist movements in Europe to America’s anti-communist McCarthyites and
Argentina’s Peronistas. As Benjamin Moffitt explains in his book “The Global
Rise of Populism”, a conference at the London School of Economics in 1967
agreed that the term, while useful, was too mushy to be tied down to a single
description. Some scholars linked it to frustration over declines in status or
welfare, some to nationalist nostalgia. Others saw it as more of a political
strategy in which a charismatic leader appeals to the masses while sweeping
aside institutions (though not all populist movements have such a leader).
Despite its fuzziness, the term’s use has grown.
In 2004 Cas Mudde, a political scientist, offered a
definition that has become increasingly influential. In his view populism is a
“thin ideology”, one that merely sets up a framework: that of a pure people
versus a corrupt elite. (He contrasts it with pluralism, which accepts the
legitimacy of many different groups.) This thin ideology can be attached to all
sorts of “thick” ideologies with more moving parts, such as socialism,
nationalism, anti-imperialism or racism, in order to explain the world and
justify specific agendas. Poland’s Mr Kaczynski, a religious-nationalist
populist, pushes for a Catholic takeover of his country’s institutions from
elite secular liberals. The Dutch Mr Wilders, a secular-nationalist populist,
demands a crackdown on Islam (in defence of gay rights) and reviles the
multicultural elite. Spain’s Podemos, an anarchist-socialist populist party,
pushes to seize vacant buildings owned by banks and distribute them to the
poor, and attacks “la casta” (the elite caste).
This “thin ideology” definition of populism seems apt
in Britain, where Brexiteers denounce experts, refer to themselves as “the
people” and boast of having “smashed the elite”. Indeed, Brexit seems to lack a
unified “thick ideology”: Brexiteers have different attitudes to trade, race, government
spending and almost everything else. But other scholars feel that the
thin-ideology definition fails to capture some dimensions. Jan-Werner Müller, a
political scientist, thinks populists are defined by their claim that they
alone represent the people, and that all others are illegitimate. And there are
important distinctions within the category, such as that between inclusive and
exclusive varieties. Exclusive populism focuses on shutting out stigmatised
groups (refugees, Roma), and is more common in Europe. Inclusive populism
demands that politics be opened up to stigmatised groups (the poor,
minorities), and is more common in Latin America. Mr Mudde argues that while
most writers deplore populism, its upside lies in forcing elites to discuss issues
they prefer to ignore. But populism’s belief that the people are always right
is bad news for two elements of liberal democracy: the rights of minorities and
the rule of law.
No comments:
Post a Comment