Last week, the Supreme Court issued a summary reversal to enforce its own
clear and on-point precedent. In doing so, the court reminded the lower courts
of how authoritative it is. For instance, the court intoned that “it is this
Court’s prerogative alone to overrule one of its precedents” and that those
precedents “bound” the lower court whose decision was under review. The summary
reversal fits a familiar picture of vertical “stare decisis,” in which the
court issues formal precedents that lower courts are absolutely obliged to
follow – and absolutely may not overrule.
There’s something
undeniably right about that point of view. After all, lower courts don’t often
declare that they’ve simply rejected or overruled the Supreme Court’s
decisions. And many lower-court decisions are replete with claims of faithful
adherence to higher-court precedent. When dissenting judges say that
lower-court majorities haven’t followed Supreme Court precedent, they’re
throwing shade.
But this
conventional view of vertical stare decisis is too simple to describe reality
and, on reflection, is actually unappealing. I suspect that anyone reading this
post can easily think of cases in which lower courts strained to avoid
following higher-court decisions. And at least some of those efforts seem
defensible. While the Supreme Court may claim decision-making expertise and
unique authority, it’s still an imperfect institution. And lower courts are
sometimes able to spot when the Supreme Court has written too broadly to
account for legal nuances or the possibility of factual change.
To account for the
complex role of Supreme Court precedent, we need a concept that lies between
overruling and following higher-court rulings. In a recent paper, I tried to address that need by introducing the idea
of “narrowing from below,” or construing the scope of a higher-court precedent
in a way that is more limited than the best available reading. Narrowing is an
interpretive activity. Rather than recognizing that a precedent has a certain
scope and then overriding it based on a deeper source of law, as occurs in
overruling, narrowing construes the higher-court precedent not to apply in the
first place.
Of course, narrowing from below can still pose a substantial
challenge to the Supreme Court’s authority, as well as a risk of disuniformity.
So when Supreme Court precedent is relevantly clear, narrowing from below is
generally no more legitimate than overruling from below.
But when Supreme Court
precedent is relevantly ambiguous, then narrowing is often legitimate, even
though it means not adhering to the best available reading of precedent. The
high court, after all, isn’t the only source of law relevant to lower courts.
When dealing with unclear case law, lower courts are often justified in erring
on the side of their own first-principles views of the constitutional or other
law at issue. Indeed, the Supreme Court’s decision to issue unclear precedent
can be understood as a kind of delegation to lower courts, authorizing them to
make adjustments in light of their own distinctive knowledge and opinions. And
when the court’s precedent is unclear, affected parties usually know not to
rely too strongly on what seems like the best available reading.
Once you know what to
look for, narrowing from below is fairly easy to find. Take the court’s Second
Amendment jurisprudence. District
of Columbia v. Heller,
in which the court struck down a law banning handguns, seemed to establish a
fairly rigid historical test for Second Amendment claims, prompting Justice
John Paul Stevens’s four-justice dissent to “fear that the District’s policy
choice may well be just the first of an unknown number of dominoes to be
knocked off the table.” But very few dominoes ever fell, with the thanks (or
blame) going to the lower courts that quickly tamed Heller and curtailed its implications.
Recognizing this pattern in a Second Amendment case, Judge Alice Batchelder recently cited my paper on
the subject in positing that “[i]t is the lower courts, both we and our sister
circuits, that have … engag[ed] in ‘narrowing from below.’”
But narrowing from below
has no inherent ideological valence and has recently been used to curb a range
of precedents. Perhaps the starkest and most troubling example involves Boumediene
v. Bush, in
which the court ruled that foreign nationals held at Guantanamo Bay have a
right to pursue habeas corpus challenges to their detention. The precedential
legacy of Boumediene has largely been left to the U.S.
Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit. Remarkably, a number of D.C. Circuit
judges have expressly criticized Boumediene as
wrongheaded while construing it narrowly, prompting Judge David Tatel and others to cry
foul. For example, law professor Janet Cooper Alexander has made a forceful case that the D.C.
Circuit has “effectively overruled” Boumediene.
The concept of narrowing
from below allows us to describe what has happened more precisely. The D.C.
Circuit hasn’t asserted a power to overrule from below, nor has it contravened
the clear meaning of Boumediene. Instead, the appellate court has construed Boumediene’s ambiguities in favor of its
inapplicability. Whether the D.C. Circuit’s actions are impermissible depends
in part on one’s theory of vertical stare decisis. If lower courts should
predict the Supreme Court’s desires, then perhaps the D.C. Circuit has acted
legitimately. After all, the Supreme Court hasn’t seen fit to intervene. But if
lower courts have a duty to treat the Supreme Court’s case law as authoritative
even when incorrect, then the D.C. Circuit would be acting illegitimately by
narrowing higher-court precedent based on disagreement with it.
The Heller and Boumediene examples
might create the impression that narrowing from below necessarily diminishes
the Supreme Court’s power. But the reality is more complicated. True, narrowing
from below enables lower courts to act on their own views of the law and to
influence the high court’s agenda (such as by creating or avoiding circuit
splits). But the Supreme Court itself has a great deal to say about when
narrowing from below takes place. By asserting clear rules, the Supreme Court
can preclude legitimate narrowing from below – and make any kind of narrowing
from below harder to do. And, of course, the Supreme Court stands ready to add
new clarity or correct outliers, including through summary reversals like the
one it issued last week.
Moreover, the high court
might actually benefit from narrowing from below even when the justices don’t
consciously invite it. In many cases, I’ve argued, narrowing from below
“helpfully informs the Court of the consequences of updating the law in one
direction or another.” The court often has a great deal to learn from the way
that lower courts choose to narrow. And a more informed Supreme Court may be
better equipped to set wise national precedent. So, in many situations,
narrowing from below actually enhances the Supreme Court’s effectiveness.
Recent Fourth Amendment
case law supplies a good example. In a Fourth Amendment case from 1973, the
court set a fairly categorical rule allowing for searches of persons incident to
their lawful arrest. That rule may have been defensible when issued, but
technological changes eventually rendered it defective. Today, most people
carry a large part of their lives in their smartphones, making personal
searches highly intrusive. In response to that development, a number of lower
courts construed the 1973 decision narrowly, so that it didn’t apply to
smartphones. These decisions were highly controversial, and there was a strong
argument that they contravened the best reading of an avowedly categorical
precedent. But when the Supreme Court ruled on the issue in 2014 in Riley
v. California, it
criticized decisions that had “mechanical[ly]” adhered to the 1973 case and
praised lower courts that had stretched the case law to update it.
What’s more, the high
court invites narrowing not just through conventional precedents but also
through “signals,” or official but informal guidance on how lower courts should
decide cases. Thanks to new communications technologies and the legal culture
of court-watching, the justices can now provide many informal cues outside of
full-dress decisions on the merits, such as by denying or granting stays or
making their views clear at oral argument. Signals could be viewed as occupying
a new precedential tier below full merits decisions. That is, signals might
properly be used to resolve cases of first impression or to construe
ambiguities in conventional precedent, but not to trump clear majority rulings.
One important way of
using signals is to green-light narrowing from below. Imagine that the Supreme
Court lacks the opportunity – or the confidence – to scale back one of its
merits decisions but nonetheless hopes to suggest how lower courts should
proceed. In those circumstances, the court could profitably signal that
narrowing from below is permissible, so as to allow for lower-court
experimentation. Or, going further, the court might signal precisely how lower
courts should deal with a precedential ambiguity. The ability to issue these
signals could have supervisory benefits – but they must be viewed cautiously.
Because signals are informal, they are easily misinterpreted, so lower courts
should generally follow them only when they have been issued deliberately by a
majority of the justices.
Remarkably, some courts
have expressly debated whether to follow the Supreme Court’s signals. For
instance, in DeBoer
v. Snyder, the U. S. Court of Appeals for the 6th Circuit
entertained – but ultimately rejected – the possibility that the Supreme
Court’s then-recent denials of petitions for review in same-sex marriage cases
might “signal that, from the Court’s perspective, the right to same-sex
marriage is inevitable.” Clearly, denials of review aren’t conventional
precedent. But those particular denials sent a strong signal that lower courts
should no longer feel bound by Baker v. Nelson, a 1972 summary decision in which the Supreme Court
had ruled against same-sex marriage rights.
More recently, the 8th
Circuit discerned “a signal” in the
Supreme Court’s remarkable stay orders related to contraception coverage under
the Affordable Care Act. Other courts had also discussed those signals, with
varying results. So when the high court finally addressed the issue in Zubik
v. Burwell,
Justice Sonia Sotomayor wrote separately (joined by Justice Ruth Bader
Ginsburg) in part to assert that “[l]ower courts … should not construe either
today’s per curiam or our order of March 29, 2016, as signals of where this
Court stands.” The fact that two justices felt that they had to issue this
caution – and that they did so without the endorsement of a majority –
demonstrates that signals are playing an important role in the judicial system.
In short, the
precedential universe is now too complex to rely only on the familiar concepts
of following and overruling, or to limit one’s view to conventional precedent.
Narrowing from below and Supreme Court signals have become an important part of
the story.
No comments:
Post a Comment