George Akerlof’s 1970 paper, “The
Market for Lemons”, is a foundation stone of information economics. The first
in our series on seminal economic ideas
IN 2007 the state of Washington introduced a new rule
aimed at making the labour market fairer: firms were banned from checking job
applicants’ credit scores. Campaigners celebrated the new law as a step towards
equality—an applicant with a low credit score is much more likely to be poor,
black or young. Since then, ten other states have followed suit. But when
Robert Clifford and Daniel Shoag, two economists, recently studied the bans,
they found that the laws left blacks and the young with fewer jobs, not more.
Before 1970, economists would not have found much in
their discipline to help them mull this puzzle. Indeed, they did not think very
hard about the role of information at all. In the labour market, for example,
the textbooks mostly assumed that employers know the productivity of their
workers—or potential workers—and, thanks to competition, pay them for exactly
the value of what they produce.
You might think that research upending that conclusion
would immediately be celebrated as an important breakthrough. Yet when, in the
late 1960s, George Akerlof wrote “The Market for Lemons”, which did just that,
and later won its author a Nobel prize, the paper was rejected by three leading
journals. At the time, Mr Akerlof was an assistant professor at the University
of California, Berkeley; he had only completed his PhD, at MIT, in 1966.
Perhaps as a result, the American
Economic Review thought his paper’s insights trivial. The Review
of Economic Studiesagreed.
The Journal
of Political Economy had almost the opposite concern: it could not stomach
the paper’s implications. Mr Akerlof, now an emeritus professor at Berkeley and
married to Janet Yellen, the chairman of the Federal Reserve, recalls the
editor’s complaint: “If this is correct, economics would be different.”
In a way, the editors
were all right. Mr Akerlof’s idea, eventually published in the Quarterly
Journal of Economics in 1970, was at once simple and revolutionary. Suppose
buyers in the used-car market value good cars—“peaches”—at $1,000, and sellers
at slightly less. A malfunctioning used car—a “lemon”—is worth only $500 to
buyers (and, again, slightly less to sellers). If buyers can tell lemons and
peaches apart, trade in both will flourish. In reality, buyers might struggle
to tell the difference: scratches can be touched up, engine problems left
undisclosed, even odometers tampered with.
To account for the risk
that a car is a lemon, buyers cut their offers. They might be willing to pay,
say, $750 for a car they perceive as having an even chance of being a lemon or
a peach. But dealers who know for sure they have a peach will reject such an
offer. As a result, the buyers face “adverse selection”: the only sellers who
will be prepared to accept $750 will be those who know they are offloading a
lemon.
Smart buyers can foresee
this problem. Knowing they will only ever be sold a lemon, they offer only
$500. Sellers of lemons end up with the same price as they would have done were
there no ambiguity. But peaches stay in the garage. This is a tragedy: there
are buyers who would happily pay the asking-price for a peach, if only they
could be sure of the car’s quality. This “information asymmetry” between buyers
and sellers kills the market.
Is it really true that
you can win a Nobel prize just for observing that some people in markets know
more than others? That was the question one journalist asked of Michael Spence,
who, along with Mr Akerlof and Joseph Stiglitz, was a joint recipient of the
2001 Nobel award for their work on information asymmetry. His incredulity was
understandable. The lemons paper was not even an accurate description of the
used-car market: clearly not every used car sold is a dud. And insurers had
long recognised that their customers might be the best judges of what risks
they faced, and that those keenest to buy insurance were probably the riskiest
bets.
Yet the idea was new to
mainstream economists, who quickly realised that it made many of their models
redundant. Further breakthroughs soon followed, as researchers examined how the
asymmetry problem could be solved. Mr Spence’s flagship contribution was a 1973
paper called “Job Market Signalling” that looked at the labour market. Employers
may struggle to tell which job candidates are best. Mr Spence showed that top
workers might signal their talents to firms by collecting gongs, like college
degrees. Crucially, this only works if the signal is credible: if
low-productivity workers found it easy to get a degree, then they could
masquerade as clever types.
This idea turns
conventional wisdom on its head. Education is usually thought to benefit
society by making workers more productive. If it is merely a signal of talent,
the returns to investment in education flow to the students, who earn a higher
wage at the expense of the less able, and perhaps to universities, but not to
society at large. One disciple of the idea, Bryan Caplan of George Mason
University, is currently penning a book entitled “The Case Against Education”.
(Mr Spence himself regrets that others took his theory as a literal description
of the world.)
Signalling helps explain
what happened when Washington and those other states stopped firms from
obtaining job-applicants’ credit scores. Credit history is a credible signal:
it is hard to fake, and, presumably, those with good credit scores are more
likely to make good employees than those who default on their debts. Messrs
Clifford and Shoag found that when firms could no longer access credit scores,
they put more weight on other signals, like education and experience. Because
these are rarer among disadvantaged groups, it became harder, not easier, for
them to convince employers of their worth.
Signalling explains all
kinds of behaviour. Firms pay dividends to their shareholders, who must pay
income tax on the payouts. Surely it would be better if they retained their
earnings, boosting their share prices, and thus delivering their shareholders
lightly taxed capital gains? Signalling solves the mystery: paying a dividend
is a sign of strength, showing that a firm feels no need to hoard cash. By the
same token, why might a restaurant deliberately locate in an area with high
rents? It signals to potential customers that it believes its good food will
bring it success.
Signalling is not the
only way to overcome the lemons problem. In a 1976 paper Mr Stiglitz and
Michael Rothschild, another economist, showed how insurers might “screen” their
customers. The essence of screening is to offer deals which would only ever
attract one type of punter.
Suppose a car insurer
faces two different types of customer, high-risk and low-risk. They cannot tell
these groups apart; only the customer knows whether he is a safe driver. Messrs
Rothschild and Stiglitz showed that, in a competitive market, insurers cannot
profitably offer the same deal to both groups. If they did, the premiums of
safe drivers would subsidise payouts to reckless ones. A rival could offer a
deal with slightly lower premiums, and slightly less coverage, which would peel
away only safe drivers because risky ones prefer to stay fully insured. The
firm, left only with bad risks, would make a loss. (Some worried a related
problem would afflict Obamacare, which forbids American health insurers from
discriminating against customers who are already unwell: if the resulting high
premiums were to deter healthy, young customers from signing up, firms might
have to raise premiums further, driving more healthy customers away in a so-called
“death spiral”.)
The car insurer must offer two deals, making sure that
each attracts only the customers it is designed for. The trick is to offer one
pricey full-insurance deal, and an alternative cheap option with a sizeable
deductible. Risky drivers will balk at the deductible, knowing that there is a
good chance they will end up paying it when they claim. They will fork out for
expensive coverage instead. Safe drivers will tolerate the high deductible and
pay a lower price for what coverage they do get.
This is not a
particularly happy resolution of the problem. Good drivers are stuck with high
deductibles—just as in Spence’s model of education, highly productive workers
must fork out for an education in order to prove their worth. Yet screening is
in play almost every time a firm offers its customers a menu of options.
Airlines, for instance,
want to milk rich customers with higher prices, without driving away poorer
ones. If they knew the depth of each customer’s pockets in advance, they could
offer only first-class tickets to the wealthy, and better-value tickets to
everyone else. But because they must offer everyone the same options, they must
nudge those who can afford it towards the pricier ticket. That means
deliberately making the standard cabin uncomfortable, to ensure that the only
people who slum it are those with slimmer wallets.
Hazard undercuts Eden
Adverse selection has a
cousin. Insurers have long known that people who buy insurance are more likely
to take risks. Someone with home insurance will check their smoke alarms less
often; health insurance encourages unhealthy eating and drinking. Economists
first cottoned on to this phenomenon of “moral hazard” when Kenneth Arrow wrote
about it in 1963.
Moral hazard occurs when
incentives go haywire. The old economics, noted Mr Stiglitz in his Nobel-prize
lecture, paid considerable lip-service to incentives, but had remarkably little
to say about them. In a completely transparent world, you need not worry about
incentivising someone, because you can use a contract to specify their
behaviour precisely. It is when information is asymmetric and you cannot
observe what they are doing (is your tradesman using cheap parts? Is your
employee slacking?) that you must worry about ensuring that interests are aligned.
Such scenarios pose what
are known as “principal-agent” problems. How can a principal (like a manager)
get an agent (like an employee) to behave how he wants, when he cannot monitor
them all the time? The simplest way to make sure that an employee works hard is
to give him some or all of the profit. Hairdressers, for instance, will often
rent a spot in a salon and keep their takings for themselves.
But hard work does not
always guarantee success: a star analyst at a consulting firm, for example, might
do stellar work pitching for a project that nonetheless goes to a rival. So,
another option is to pay “efficiency wages”. Mr Stiglitz and Carl Shapiro,
another economist, showed that firms might pay premium wages to make employees
value their jobs more highly. This, in turn, would make them less likely to
shirk their responsibilities, because they would lose more if they were caught
and got fired. That insight helps to explain a fundamental puzzle in economics:
when workers are unemployed but want jobs, why don’t wages fall until someone
is willing to hire them? An answer is that above-market wages act as a carrot,
the resulting unemployment, a stick.
And this reveals an even
deeper point. Before Mr Akerlof and the other pioneers of information economics
came along, the discipline assumed that in competitive markets, prices reflect
marginal costs: charge above cost, and a competitor will undercut you. But in a
world of information asymmetry, “good behaviour is driven by earning a surplus
over what one could get elsewhere,” according to Mr Stiglitz. The wage must be
higher than what a worker can get in another job, for them to want to avoid the
sack; and firms must find it painful to lose customers when their product is
shoddy, if they are to invest in quality. In markets with imperfect
information, price cannot equal marginal cost.
The concept of
information asymmetry, then, truly changed the discipline. Nearly 50 years
after the lemons paper was rejected three times, its insights remain of crucial relevance to
economists, and to economic policy. Just ask any young, black Washingtonian
with a good credit score who wants to find a job.
No comments:
Post a Comment