Friday, June 17, 2016

Hans-Georg Gadamer: Hermeneutics

Hermeneutics concerns itself with the philosophy of interpretation, initially oriented toward the interpretation of texts. Indeed, though its origins lay in Greek antiquity, ‘advances in the formulation of methods of interpretation had to await the Reformation and the attack on the Church’s authority to interpret the bible.’1 Thus, hermeneutics was a branch of theology that dealt specifically with the interpretation of holy scriptures but has since expanded beyond textual interpretation to encompass the interpretation of verbal (speech) and non-verbal (conduct) expressions.


The use of Gadamerian hermeneutics in legal interpretation is well documented. Indeed, Gadamer regarded law as having ‘exemplary significance’ in developing his Post-Romantic interpretation that moved beyond methodological variations of attempting to determine authorial (specifically here, legislative) intent (literal, mischief or golden rule). 

Importantly, as the intellectual progeny of Heidegger, Gadamer’s hermeneutics moved in a way similar to that of his mentor.2 Like Heidegger’s concept of phronesis for example, that emphasises our practical being-in-the-world and identified our concrete situation as the mode of knowledge, Gadamer similarly employed this ‘thrownness’ (geworfenheit), by refuting the possibility of an interpretive style that was able to transcend our necessary situatedness. Additionally, his dialogic approach, explained later as the Fusion of Horizons, is eminently Heideggerean. Gadamer thus resisted attempting to articulate a timelessmethod of hermeneutics and was more intrigued by identifying theconditions of the interpretive style.

Gadamer stated that ‘understanding is, essentially, a historically effected event’.3 He therefore rejected objective, neutral or value-free readings of legal texts, instead explaining what the conditions were for intersubjective meaning or Verständigung. These can be understood in three ways; that interpretation is ‘ontological, dialectical and critical’.4

That interpretation is ontological derives from Gadamer’s assertion that the truth is largely independent of any method and that we are in fact interpretive beings. Here, he adopted Heidegger’s historicity of our ‘being-in-the-world as the fore-structure of Dasein’:

We are thrown into a world whose contexts moulds us and limits our imagination and, hence, our options. Our very being is a process of interpreting our past, which is projected onto us and to which we respond…not in what way being can be understood but in what way understanding is being…interpretation is the common ground of interaction between text and interpreter, by which each establishes its being…interpreter and text are indissolubly linked as a matter of being.4

To put it crudely, interpretation is not something one ‘does’, but rather something one ‘is’. Hence to think of variable methods of interpretation, like the Romantics did, missed the point. Unlike the tabula rasa of the Cartesian spectator or Kant’s transcendental concepts for examplewhat shaped one’s understanding of a text is one’s horizon which is ‘the range of vision that includes everything that can be seen from a particular vantage point’.6 This relates to what Gadamer calls the history of effect.7 As our existence is inherently contextual, we project onto meaning the traditions of the world in which we are ‘thrown into’. 

Thus one possesses an ‘effective historical consciousness’ by stint of awareness of this situatedness.Understanding is thus contingent on a temporality in which ‘time is the productive possibility of custom and tradition aiding understanding by illuminating what presents itself’.8 A ‘Gadamerian judge’ therefore would be defined and shaped by an immanent effective history which it is necessarily immersed in and thus constituted by.

That interpretation is dialectical refers to the to-ing and fro-ing between the horizons of the interpreter and the (legal) text. Meaning does not protrude from the text automatically (like authorial intent claims) but requires participation.9 Probing and further penetration of the text challenges the interpreter’s own horizon.10 Indeed, ‘the confrontation with the text and openness is willingness to expose, challenge and criticise prejudices highlighted by the text. 

This openness is achieved dialectically with a willingness to listen and also to admit error’.11 Further, ‘an important part of this testing occurs in encountering the past and in understanding the tradition from which we come’.12 The dialectical process with the text will eventually result in a Fusion of Horizons in which the interpreters’ prejudgments, generated by their effective history, are exposed and challenged—as is the text’s, stimulating introspection into the effective history of the interpreter and the presumptions of the text. 

Through conversation, a synthesis of sorts is accomplished. In its standard application to statutory interpretation therefore, hermeneutics is a dialogic process.13 Rather than trying to uncover some mystical, psychological intent of the author of a legal text, the judge ‘instead challenges and questions its assumptions to get at its truth-value. Similarly, the interpreter places her own pre-judgments at risk, by opening them to questions and challenges from the text’.14

That interpretation is critical; ‘the interpreter questions the text, the presuppositions of which may be attenuated or undermined over time. In turn, the interpreter uses the experience to re-evaluate her own pre-understandings, to separate the enabling, truth-seeking ones from the disabling, false ones’.4 Thus the meaning of legal texts are not static but dynamic. 

Hermeneutics confronts the embedded prejudices of the legal text by colliding them with the similar prejudices of the judicial interpreter. Gadamerian hermeneutics therefore, is able to provide a sounder account of so-called ‘departures from established precedent’. For example, the case of Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka16 in which the US Supreme Court declared racially segregated schools as unconstitutional, overturned the state-sponsored segregation of the earlier case of Plessy v. Ferguson17where both cases relied upon divergent interpretive readings of the 14thAmendment’s Equal Protection Clause. Indeed, in confronting the prejudices of the legal text head on (both the amendment and the case law), Justice Warren was documented as having convened a meeting of the Justices and saying that maintaining the precedent of Plessy was to sustain the belief in the inferiority of African-Americans. 

Problematically for Romantic Hermeneutics therefore, which was based on a misplaced claim of transcendental meaning, such endeavours undermined the critical scope of hermeneutics. Indeed, the author is only the first reader of the text. Arguably, the decision in Brown for the Romantics could not be considered as anything other than ‘judicial activism’.

Before Gadamer, hermeneutics (attempting to emulate the natural sciences) sought to determine the truth of texts with reference to a meaning that was the same at all places and at all times. 

However, Gadamer recognised that our necessary situatedness meant, not just that such a transcendental meaning was beyond us, but it did not ask the correct question—what were the conditions of interpretation? Specifically for law, with the popularisation of the sentiment that adjudication is interpretive18(rather than fictitiously a declarative enterprise) Gadamer’s utility in statutory interpretation has varied among scholars, some saying that it exemplified hermeneutical understanding,19 some being more reticent,20others stating it presented an honest account of statutory interpretation that avoids the limitations of other theories,21 while some suggested that we’d yet to unlock its potential.22 

Most importantly however, to not recognise our initial throwness in which our traditions shape our understanding (our ‘effective historical consciousness) is to demonstrate what Gadamer referred to as Enlightenment thinking’s ‘prejudice toward prejudice’.

Tanzil Chowdhury is a Doctoral Researcher in the School of Law, University of Manchester.

  1. Georgia Warnke, Hermeneutics, Tradition and Reason (Polity Press, 1987) 7 ↩
  2. Gadamer worked for Heidegger as an unpaid assistant ↩
  3. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, (Joel Weinheimer and Donald G Marshall trs, 2nd edn, Continuum Publishing Group 2004) 300 ↩
  4. William N Eskridge Jr. ‘Gadamer/ Statutory Interpretation’ (1990) 3832 Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship Series, 614 ↩
  5. William N Eskridge Jr. ‘Gadamer/ Statutory Interpretation’ (1990) 3832 Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship Series, 614 ↩
  6. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, (Joel Weinheimer and Donald G Marshall trs, 2nd edn, Continuum Publishing Group 2004) 301 ↩
  7. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, (Joel Weinheimer and Donald G Marshall trs, 2nd edn, Continuum Publishing Group 2004) 299–300 ↩
  8. Paul Regan ‘Hans-Georg Gadamer’s Philosophical Hermeneutics: Concepts of Reading, Understanding and Interpretation’ (2012) 4, 2 Meta: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy, 300 ↩
  9. Georgia Warnke, Hermeneutics, Tradition and Reason (Polity Press, 1987) 65 ↩
  10. Brad Sherman, ‘Hermeneutics in Law’ (1988) 51 Modern Law Review, 390↩
  11. Brad Sherman, ‘Hermeneutics in Law’ (1988) 51 Modern Law Review, 393 ↩
  12. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, (Joel Weinheimer and Donald G Marshall trs, 2nd edn, Continuum Publishing Group 2004) 306 ↩
  13. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, (Joel Weinheimer and Donald G Marshall trs, 2nd edn, Continuum Publishing Group 2004) 362–369 ↩
  14. William N Eskridge Jr. ‘Gadamer/ Statutory Interpretation’ (1990) 3832 Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship Series 623 ↩
  15. William N Eskridge Jr. ‘Gadamer/ Statutory Interpretation’ (1990) 3832 Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship Series, 614 ↩
  16. 347 U.S. 483 ↩
  17. 163 U.S. 537 ↩
  18. Rosemary Coombe ‘Same As It Ever Was: Rethinking the Politics of Legal Interpretation’ (1989) 34 McGill Law Journal 603 ↩
  19. Francis Joseph Mootz, ‘Hermeneutics and Law’ in Niall Keane and Chris Law (eds) The Blackwell Companion to Hermeneutics (Wiley & Sons, 2016) 595 ↩
  20. Brad Sherman, ‘Hermeneutics in Law’ (1988) 51 Modern Law Review, 395 ↩
  21. See also Eskridge (n 325) 609–681; George Wright, ‘On a General Theory of Interpretation: The Betti-Gadamer Dispute in Legal Hermeneutics’ (1987) 32, 1 American Journal of Jurisprudence, 191 ↩
  22. Francis Mootz, ‘Gadamer’s Rhetorical Conception of Hermeneutics as the Key to Developing a Critical Hermeneutics (2008) SSRN Electronic Journal, 1 ↩

No comments:

Post a Comment