Karl Popper on democracy
In 1988 The Economist invited the philosopher Karl
Popper to write an article on democracy. It appeared in the issue of April 23rd
that year and made the case for a two-party system. As America’s presidential
race begins, with the Iowa caucus on February 1st, we are republishing it,
below.
The first book in English by Professor Sir Karl Popper
was accepted for publication in London while Hitler’s bombs were falling, and
was published in 1945 under the title “The Open Society and its Enemies”. The
book was well received, but in this article Sir Karl questions whether his
central theory of democracy (which he does not characterise as “the rule of the
people”) has been understood.
MY THEORY of democracy is very simple and easy for everybody to understand.
But its fundamental problem is so different from the age-old theory of
democracy which everybody takes for granted that it seems that this difference
has not been grasped, just because of the simplicity of the theory. It avoids
high-sounding, abstract words like “rule”, “freedom” and “reason”. I do believe
in freedom and reason, but I do not think that one can construct a simple,
practical and fruitful theory in these terms. They are too abstract, and too
prone to be misused; and, of course, nothing whatever can be gained by their
definition.
This article is divided into three main parts. The first sets out, briefly,
what may be called the classical theory of democracy: the theory of the rule of
the people. The second is a brief sketch of my more realistic theory. The third
is, in the main, an outline of some practical applications of my theory, in
reply to the question: “What practical difference does this new theory make?”
The classical theory
The classical theory is, in brief, the theory that democracy is the rule of the people, and that the people have a right to rule. For the claim that the people have this right, many and various reasons have been given; however, it will not be necessary for me to enter into these reasons here. Instead, I will briefly examine some of the historical background of the theory, and of the terminology.
Plato was the first theoretician to make a system out of the distinctions
between what he regarded as the main forms of the city-state. According to the
number of the rulers, he distinguished between: (1) monarchy, the rule of one
good man, and tyranny, the distorted form of monarchy; (2) aristocracy, the
rule of a few good men, and oligarchy, its distorted form; (3) democracy, the
rule of the many, of all the people. Democracy did not have two forms. For the
many always formed a rabble, and so democracy was distorted in itself.
If one looks more closely at this classification, and if one asks oneself
what problem was at the back of Plato’s mind, then one finds that the following
underlay not only Plato’s classification and theory, but also those of everybody
else. From Plato to Karl Marx and beyond, the fundamental problem has always
been: who should rule the state? (One of my main points will be that this
problem must be replaced by a totally different one.) Plato’s answer was simple
and naive: “the best” should rule. If possible, “the best of all”, alone.
Next
choice: the best few, the aristocrats. But certainly not the many, the rabble,
the demos.
The Athenian practice had been, even before Plato’s birth, precisely the
opposite: the people, the demos, should rule. All important. political
decisions—such as war and peace—were made by the assembly of all full citizens.
This is now called “direct democracy”; but we must never forget that the
citizens formed a minority of the inhabitants—even of the natives. From the
point of view here adopted, the important thing is that, in practice, the
Athenian democrats regarded their democracy as the alternative to tyranny—to
arbitrary rule: in fact, they knew well that a popular leader might be invested
with tyrannical powers by a popular vote.
So they knew that a popular vote may be wrongheaded, even in the most
important matters. (The institution of ostracism recognised this: the
ostracised person was banned as a matter of precaution only; he was neither
tried nor regarded as guilty.)The Athenians were right: decisions arrived at
democratically, and even the powers conveyed upon a government by a democratic
vote, may be wrong. It is hard, if not impossible, to construct a constitution
that safeguards against mistakes. This is one of the strongest reasons for
founding the idea of democracy upon the practical principle of avoiding tyranny
rather than upon a divine, or a morally legitimate, right of the people to
rule.
The (in my opinion, vicious) principle of legitimacy plays a great part in
European history. While the Roman legions were strong, the Caesars based their
power upon the principle: the army legitimises the ruler (by acclamation). But
with the decline of the Empire, the problem of legitimacy became urgent; and this
was strongly felt by Diocletian, who tried to support the new structure of the
Imperium of the God-Caesars ideologically with traditional and religious
distinctions and the corresponding attribution of different titles: Caesar,
Augustus, Herculius, and Jovius (i.e., related to Jupiter).
Yet it seems that there was a need for a more authoritative, deeper
religious legitimation. In the next generation, monotheism in the form of
Christianity (which, of the available monotheisms, has spread most widely)
offered itself to Constantine as the solution to the problem. From then on, the
ruler ruled by the Grace of God—of the one and the only universal God. The
complete success of this new ideology of legitimacy explains both the ties and
the tensions between the spiritual and the worldly powers which thus became
mutual dependants, and therefore rivals, throughout the Middle Ages.
So, in the Middle Ages, the answer to the question “Who should rule?”
became the principle: God is the ruler, and He rules through His legitimate
human representatives. It was this principle of legitimacy which was first
seriously challenged by the Reformation and then by the English revolution of
1648-49 which proclaimed the divine right of the people to rule. But in this
revolution the divine right of the people was immediately used to establish the
dictatorship of Oliver Cromwell.
After the dictator’s death, there was a return to the older form of
legitimacy; and it was the violation of protestant legitimacy by James II, by
the legitimate monarch himself, which led to the “Glorious Revolution” of 1688,
and to the development of British democracy through a gradual strengthening of
the power of Parliament, which had legitimised William and Mary. The unique
character of this development was precisely due to the experience that
fundamental theological and ideological quarrels about who should rule lead
only to catastrophe. Royal legitimacy was no longer a reliable principle, nor
was the rule of the people. In practice, there was a monarchy of somewhat
dubious legitimacy created by the will of Parliament, and a fairly steady
increase of parliamentary power. The British became dubious about abstract
principles; and the Platonic problem “Who should rule?” was no longer seriously
raised in Britain until our own days.
Karl Marx, who was not a British politician, was still dominated by the old
Platonic problem which he saw as: “Who should rule? The good or the bad—the
workers or the capitalists?” And even those who rejected the state altogether,
in the name of freedom, could not free themselves from the fetters of a
misconceived old problem; for they called themselves anarchists—that is,
opponents of all forms of rule. One can sympathise with their unsuccessful
attempt to get away from the old problem “Who should rule?”
A more realistic theory
In “The Open Society and its Enemies” I suggested that an entirely new problem should be recognised as the fundamental problem of a rational political theory. The new problem, as distinct from the old “Who should rule?”, can be formulated as follows: how is the state to be constituted so that bad rulers can be got rid of without bloodshed, without violence?
This, in contrast to the old question, is a thoroughly practical, almost
technical, problem. And the modern so-called democracies are all good examples
of practical solutions to this problem, even though they were not consciously
designed with this problem in mind. For they all adopt what is the simplest
solution to the new problem—that is, the principle that the government can be
dismissed by a majority vote.
In theory, however, these modern democracies are still based on the old
problem, and on the completely impractical ideology that it is the people, the
whole adult population, who are, or should by rights be, the real and ultimate
and the only legitimate rulers. But, of course, nowhere do the people actually
rule. It is governments that rule (and, unfortunately, also bureaucrats, our
civil servants—or our uncivil masters, as Winston Churchill called them—whom it
is difficult, if not impossible, to make accountable for their actions).
What are the consequences of this simple and practical theory of
government? My way of putting the problem and my simple solution do not, of
course, clash with the practice of western democracies, such as the unwritten
constitution of Britain, and the many written constitutions which took the
British Parliament more or less as their model. It is this practice (and not
their theory) which my theory—my problem and its solution—tries to describe.
And, for this reason, I think that I may call it a theory of “democracy”, even
though it is emphatically not a theory of the “rule of the people”, but rather
the rule of law that postulates the bloodless dismissal of the government by a
majority vote.
My theory easily avoids the paradoxes and difficulties of the old
theory—for instance, such problems as “What has to be done if ever the people
vote to establish a dictatorship?” Of course, this is not likely to happen if
the vote is free. But it has happened. And what if it does happen? Most
constitutions in fact require far more than a majority vote to amend or change
constitutional provisions, and thus would demand perhaps a two-thirds or even a
three-quarters (“qualified”) majority for a vote against democracy. But this
demand shows that they provide for such a change; and at the same time they do
not conform to the principle that the (“unqualified”) majority will is the
ultimate source of power—that the people, through a majority vote, are entitled
to rule.
All these theoretical difficulties are avoided if one abandons the question
“Who should rule?” and replaces it by the new and practical problem: how can we
best avoid situations in which a bad ruler causes too much harm? When we say
that the best solution known to us is a constitution that allows a majority
vote to dismiss the government, then we do not say the majority vote will
always be right. We do not even say that it will usually be right. We say only
that this very imperfect procedure is the best so far invented. Winston
Churchill once said, jokingly, that democracy is the worst form of
government—with the exception of all other known forms of government.
And this is the point: anybody who has ever lived under another form of
government—that is, under a dictatorship which cannot be removed without
bloodshed—will know that a democracy, imperfect though it is, is worth fighting
for and, I believe, worth dying for. This, however, is only my personal
conviction. I should regard it as wrong to try to persuade others of it.
We could base our whole theory on this, that there are only two
alternatives known to us: either a dictatorship or some form of democracy. And
we do not base our choice on the goodness of democracy, which may be doubtful,
but solely on the evilness of a dictatorship, which is certain. Not only
because the dictator is bound to make bad use of his power, but because a
dictator, even if he were benevolent, would rob all others of their
responsibility, and thus of their human rights and duties. This is a sufficient
basis for deciding in favour of democracy—that is, a rule of law that enables
us to get rid of the government. No majority, however large, ought to be
qualified to abandon this rule of law.
Proportional representation
Such are the theoretical differences between the old and the new theories. As an example of the practical difference between the theories, I propose to examine the issue of proportional representation.
The old theory and the belief that the rule of the people, by the people,
and for the people constitutes a natural right, or a divine right, form the
background of the usual argument in favour of proportional representation. For
if people rule through their representatives, and by majority votes, then it is
essential that the numerical distribution of opinion among the representatives
mirrors as closely as possible that which prevails among those who are the real
source of legitimate power: the people themselves. Everything else will he not
only grossly unfair but against all the principles of justice.
This argument collapses if the old theory is given up, so that we can look,
more dispassionately, and perhaps without much prejudice, at the inescapable
(and possibly unintended) practical consequences of proportional
representation. And these are devastating.
First of all, proportional representation confers, even if only indirectly,
a constitutional status on political parties which they would otherwise not
attain. For I can no longer choose a person whom I trust to represent me: I can
choose only a party. And the people who may represent the party are chosen only
by the party. And while people and their opinions always deserve the greatest
respect, the opinions adopted by parties (which are typically instruments of personal
advancement and of power, with all the chances for intrigue which this implies)
are not to be identified with ordinary human opinions: they are ideologies.
In a constitution that does not provide for proportional representation,
parties need not be mentioned at all. They need not be given official status.
The electorate of each constituency sends its personal representative to the
chamber. Whether he stands alone, or whether he combines with some others to
form a party, is left to him. It is an affair he may have to explain and defend
to his electorate.
His duty is to represent the interests of all those people whom he
represents to the best of his ability. These interests will in almost all cases
be identical with those of all the citizens of the country, of the nation.
These are the interests he must pursue to the best of his knowledge. He is
personally responsible to persons.
This is the only duty and the only responsibility of the representative
that must be recognised by the constitution. If he considers that he has also a
duty to a political party, then this must be due solely to the fact that he
believes that through his connection with that party he can do his primary duty
better than without the party. Consequently it is his duty to leave the party
whenever he realises that he can do his primary duty better without that party,
or perhaps with a different party.
All this is done away with if the constitution of the state incorporates
proportional representation. For under proportional representation the
candidate seeks election solely as the representative of a party, whatever the
wording of the constitution may be. If he is elected, he is elected mainly, if
not solely, because he belongs to, and represents, a certain party. Thus, his
main loyalty must be to his party, and to the party’s ideology; not to people
(except, perhaps, the leaders of the party).
It can therefore never be his duty to vote against his party. On the
contrary, he is morally bound to the party as whose representative he was voted
into parliament. And in the event that he can no longer square this with his
conscience, it would, in my opinion, be his moral duty to resign not only from
his party but from parliament, even though the country’s constitution may place
no such obligation upon him.
In fact, the system under which he was elected robs him of personal
responsibility; it makes of him a voting machine rather than a thinking and
feeling person. In my view, this is by itself a sufficient argument against
proportional representation. For what we need in politics are individuals who
can judge on their own and who are prepared to carry personal responsibility.
Such individuals are difficult to find under any party system, even without
proportional representation—and it must be admitted that we have not yet found
a way of doing without parties. But if we have to have parties, we had better
not, by our constitution, add deliberately to the enslavement of our
representatives to the party machine and to the party ideology by introducing
proportional representation.
The immediate consequence of proportional representation is that it will
tend to increase the number of parties. This, at first glance, may seem
desirable: more parties means more choice, more opportunities, less rigidity,
more criticism. It also means a greater distribution of influence and of power.
However, this first impression is totally mistaken. The existence of many
parties means, essentially, that a coalition government becomes inevitable. It
means difficulties in the formation of any new government, and in keeping a
government together for any length of time.
Minority rule
While proportional representation is based on the idea that the influence of a party should be proportional to its voting power, a coalition government means, more often than not, that small parties can exercise a disproportionately great—and often decisive—influence, both on the formation of a government and on its resignation, and so on all its decisions. Most important of all, it means the decay of responsibility. For in a coalition government there is reduced responsibility for all the partners in the coalition.
Proportional representation—and the greater number of parties as a result
thereof—may therefore have a detrimental effect on the decisive issue of how to
get rid of a government by voting it out of office, for instance in a
parliamentary election. The voters are led to expect that perhaps none of the
parties will obtain an absolute majority.
With this expectation in their minds,
the people hardly vote against any of the parties. As a result, on election day
none of the parties is dismissed, none is convicted. Accordingly, nobody looks
on election day as a Day of Judgment; as a day when a responsible government
stands to account for its deeds and omissions, for its successes and failures,
and a responsible opposition criticises this record and explains what steps the
government ought to have taken, and why.
The loss of 5% or 10% of votes by one or other of the parties is not seen
by the voters as a verdict of “guilty”. They look at it, rather, as a temporary
fluctuation in popularity. In time, the people become used to the idea that
none of the political parties or their leaders can really be made accountable
for their decisions which may have been forced on them by the necessity to form
a coalition.
From the point of view of the new theory, election day ought to be a Day of
Judgment. As Pericles of Athens said in about 430 BC, “although only a few may
originate a policy, we are all able to judge it.” Of course, we may misjudge
it; in fact, we often do. But if we have lived through a party’s period of
power and have felt its repercussions, we have at least some qualifications for
judgment.
This presupposes that the party in power and its leaders were fully
responsible for what they were doing. This, in turn, presupposes a majority
government. But with proportional representation, even in the case of a single
party governing with an absolute majority and thrown out by a majority of
disenchanted citizens, the government may not be turned out of office. It would
rather look for the smallest party strong enough to go on ruling with its help.
Hence the censured leader of the larger party would still continue to lead
the government—in direct opposition to the majority vote and on the basis of
help received from one of the small parties whose policies, in theory, may be
far removed from “representing the will of the people”. Of course, the small
party may not be strongly represented in the new government. But its power will
be very great since it may topple the government at any time. All this grossly
violates the idea that lies at the root of proportional representation: the
idea that the influence exercised by any party must correspond to the number of
votes it can muster.
The two-party system
In order to make a majority government probable, we need something approaching a two-party system, as in Britain and in the United States. Since the existence of the practice of proportional representation makes such a possibility hard to attain, I suggest that, in the interest of parliamentary responsibility, we should resist the perhaps-tempting idea that democracy demands proportional representation. Instead, we should strive for a two-party system, or at least for an approximation to it, for such a system encourages a continual process of self-criticism by the two parties.
Such a view will, however, provoke frequently voiced objections to the two-party system that merit examination: “A two-party system represses the formation of other parties.” This is correct. But considerable changes are apparent within the two major parties in Britain as well as in the United States. So the repression need not be a denial of flexibility.
The point is that in a two-party system the defeated party is liable to
take an electoral defeat seriously. So it may look for an internal reform of
its aims, which is an ideological reform. If the party is defeated twice in
succession, or even three times, the search for new ideas may become frantic,
which obviously is a healthy development. This is likely to happen, even if the
loss of votes was not very great.
Under a system with many parties, and with coalitions, this is not likely
to happen. Especially when the loss of votes is small, both the party bosses
and the electorate are inclined to take the change quietly. They regard it as
part of the game—since none of the parties had clear responsibilities.
A
democracy needs parties that are more sensitive than that and, if possible,
constantly on the alert. Only in this way can they be induced to be
self-critical. As things stand, an inclination to self-criticism after an
electoral defeat is far more pronounced in countries with a two-party system
than in those where there are several parties. In practice, then, a two-party
system is likely to be more flexible than a multi-party system, contrary to
first impressions.
It is said: “Proportional representation gives a new party a chance to
rise. Without it, the chance is much diminished. And the mere existence of a
third party may greatly improve the performance of the two big parties.” This
may well be the case. But what if five or six such new parties emerge? As we
have seen, even one small party may wield quite disproportionate power if it is
in the position to decide which of the two big parties it will join to form a
coalition government.
It is also said: “A two-party system is incompatible with the idea of an
open society—with the openness for new ideas, and with the idea of pluralism.”
Reply: both Britain and the United States are very open to new ideas. Complete
openness would, of course, be self-defeating, as would be complete freedom.
Also cultural openness and political openness are two different things. And
more important even than opening wider and wider the political debate may be a
proper attitude towards the political Day of Judgment.
No comments:
Post a Comment